The Ethics
Benedict de Spinoza
-
I. CONCERNING GOD.
-
-
I. CONCERNING GOD. DEFINITIONS.
-
I. CONCERNING GOD. AXOIMS.
-
I. CONCERNING GOD. PROPOSITIONS.
-
-
I-I. Substance is by nature prior to its modifications.
-
I-II. Two substances, whose attributes are different, have nothing in common.
-
I-III. Things which have nothing in common cannot be one the cause of the other.
-
I-IV. Two or more distinct things are distinguished one from the other
-
I-V. There cannot exist in the universe two or more substances having the same nature or attribute.
-
I-VI. One substance cannot be produced by another substance.
-
I-VII. Existence belongs to the nature of substances.
-
I-VIII. Every substance is necessarily infinite.
-
I-IX. The more reality or being a thing has, the greater the number of its attributes (Def. iv.).
-
I-X. Each particular attribute of the one substance must be conceived through itself.
-
I-XI. God, or substance, consisting of infinite attributes, of which each expresses eternal and infinite essentiality, necessarily exists.
-
I-XII. No attribute of substance can be conceived from which it would follow that substance can be divided.
-
I-XIII. Substance absolutely infinite is indivisible.
-
I-XIV. Besides God no substance can be granted or conceived.
-
I-XV. Whatsoever is, is in God, and without God nothing can be, or be conceived.
-
I-XVI. From the necessity of the divine nature must follow an infinite number of things
-
I-XVII. God acts solely by the laws of his own nature, and is not constrained by anyone.
-
I-XVIII. God is the indwelling and not the transient cause of all things.
-
I-XIX. God, and all the attributes of God, are eternal.
-
I-XX. The existence of God and his essence are one and the same.
-
I-XXI. All things which follow from the absolute nature of any attribute of God
-
I-XXII. Whatsoever follows from any attribute of God, in so far as
-
I-XXIII. Every mode, which exists both necessarily and as infinite
-
I-XXIV. The essence of things produced by God does not involve existence.
-
I-XXV. God is the efficient cause not only of the existence of things, but also of their essence.
-
I-XXVI. A thing which is conditioned to act in a particular manner
-
I-XXVII. A thing, which has been conditioned by God to act in a particular way, cannot render itself unconditioned.
-
I-XXVIII. Every individual thing, or everything which is finite and has a conditioned existence
-
I-XXIX. Nothing in the universe is contingent, but all things are conditioned
-
I-XXX. Intellect, in function (actu) finite, or in function infinite
-
I-XXXI. The intellect in function, whether finite or infinite, as will, desire, love
-
I-XXXII. Will cannot be called a free cause, but only a necessary cause.
-
I-XXXIII. Things could not have been brought into being by God
-
I-XXXIV. God’s power is identical with his essence.
-
I-XXXV. Whatsoever we conceive to be in the power of God, necessarily exists.
-
I-XXXVI. There is no cause from whose nature some effect does not follow.
-
I. CONCERNING GOD. APPENDIX.
-
-
-
II. ON THE NATURE AND ORIGIN OF THE MIND.
-
-
II. ON THE NATURE AND ORIGIN OF THE MIND. PREFACE.
-
II. ON THE NATURE AND ORIGIN OF THE MIND. DEFINITIONS.
-
II. ON THE NATURE AND ORIGIN OF THE MIND. AXIOMS.
-
II. ON THE NATURE AND ORIGIN OF THE MIND. POSTULATES.
-
II. ON THE NATURE AND ORIGIN OF THE MIND. PROPOSITIONS.
-
-
II-I. Thought is an attribute of God, or God is a thinking thing.
-
II-II. Extension is an attribute of God, or God is an extended thing.
-
II-III. In God there is necessarily the idea not only of his essence
-
II-IV. The idea of God, from which an infinite number of things follow in infinite ways, can only be one.
-
II-V. The actual being of ideas owns God as its cause, only in so far as he is considered
-
II-VI. The modes of any given attribute are caused by God, in so far as he is considered
-
II-VII. The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things.
-
II-VIII. The ideas of particular things, or of modes, that do not exist
-
II-IX. The idea of an individual thing actually existing is caused by God
-
II-X. The being of substance does not appertain to the essence of man
-
II-XI. The first element, which constitutes the actual being of the human mind
-
II-XII. Whatsoever comes to pass in the object of the idea, which constitutes the human mind
-
II-XIII. The object of the idea constituting the human mind is the body
-
II-XIV. The human mind is capable of perceiving a great number of things
-
II-XV. The idea, which constitutes the actual being of the human mind
-
II-XVI. The idea of every mode, in which the human body is affected by external bodies
-
II-XVII. If the human body is affected in a manner which involves the nature of any external body
-
II-XVIII. If the human body has once been affected by two or more bodies at the same time
-
II-XIX. The human mind has no knowledge of the body, and does not know it to exist
-
II-XX. The idea or knowledge of the human mind is also in God
-
II-XXI. This idea of the mind is united to the mind in the same way as the mind is united to the body.
-
II-XXII. The human mind perceives not only the modifications of the body, but also the ideas of such modifications.
-
II-XXIII. The mind does not know itself, except in so far as it perceives the ideas of the modifications of the body.
-
II-XXIV. The human mind does not involve an adequate knowledge of the parts composing the human body.
-
II-XXV. The idea of each modification of the human body does not involve an adequate knowledge of the external body.
-
II-XXVI. The human mind does not perceive any external body as actually existing
-
II-XXVII. The idea of each modification of the human body does not involve
-
II-XXVIII. The ideas of the modifications of the human body, in so far as
-
II-XXIX. The idea of the idea of each modification of the human body does not involve an adequate knowledge of the human mind.
-
II-XXX. We can only have a very inadequate knowledge of the duration of our body.
-
II-XXXI. We can only have a very inadequate knowledge of the duration of particular things external to ourselves.
-
II-XXXII. All ideas, in so far as they are referred to God, are true.
-
II-XXXIII. There is nothing positive in ideas, which causes them to be called false.
-
II-XXXIV. Every idea, which in us is absolute or adequate and perfect, is true.
-
II-XXXV. Falsity consists in the privation of knowledge, which inadequate, fragmentary, or confused ideas involve.
-
II-XXXVI. Inadequate and confused ideas follow by the same necessity, as adequate
-
II-XXXVII. That which is common to all (cf. Lemma II., above), and which is equally
-
II-XXXVIII. Those things, which are common to all, and which are equally in a part
-
II-XXXIX. That, which is common to and a property of the human body and such other bodies
-
II-XL. Whatsoever ideas in the mind follow from ideas which are therein adequate, are also themselves adequate.
-
II-XLI. Knowledge of the first kind is the only source of falsity, knowledge of the second and third kinds is necessarily true.
-
II-XLII. Knowledge of the second and third kinds, not knowledge of the first kind, teaches us to distinguish the true from the false.
-
II-XLIII. He, who has a true idea, simultaneously knows that he has a true idea, and cannot doubt of the truth of the thing perceived.
-
II-XLIV. It is not in the nature of reason to regard things as contingent, but as necessary.
-
II-XLV. Every idea of every body, or of every particular thing actually existing, necessarily involves the eternal and infinite essence of God.
-
II-XLVI. The knowledge of the eternal and infinite essence of God which every idea involves is adequate and perfect.
-
II-XLVII. The human mind has an adequate knowledge of the eternal and infinite essence of God.
-
II-XLVIII. In the mind there is no absolute or free will; but the mind is determined
-
II-XLIX. There is in the mind no volition or affirmation and negation, save that which an idea, inasmuch as it is an idea, involves.
-
-
-
III. ON THE ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE EMOTIONS.
-
-
III. ON THE ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE EMOTIONS. DEFINITIONS.
-
III. ON THE ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE EMOTIONS. POSTULATES.
-
III. ON THE ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE EMOTIONS. PROPOSITIONS.
-
-
III-I. Our mind is in certain cases active, and in certain cases passive.
-
III-II. Body cannot determine mind to think, neither can mind determine body
-
III-III. The activities of the mind arise solely from adequate ideas
-
III-IV. Nothing can be destroyed, except by a cause external to itself.
-
III-V. Things are naturally contrary, that is, cannot exist in the same object
-
III-VI. Everything, in so far as it is in itself, endeavours to persist in its own being.
-
III-VII. The endeavour, wherewith everything endeavours to persist in its own being, is nothing else but the actual essence of the thing in question.
-
III-VIII. The endeavour, whereby a thing endeavours to persist in its own being, involves no finite time, but an indefinite time.
-
III-IX. The mind, both in so far as it has clear and distinct ideas, and also in so far as it has confused ideas
-
III-X. An idea, which excludes the existence of our body, cannot be postulated in our mind, but is contrary thereto.
-
III-XI. Whatsoever increases or diminishes, helps or hinders the power of activity in our body, the idea thereof increases or diminishes
-
III-XII. The mind, as far as it can, endeavours to conceive those things, which increase or help the power of activity in the body.
-
III-XIII. When the mind conceives things which diminish or hinder the body’s power of activity, it endeavours, as far as possible
-
III-XIV. If the mind has once been affected by two emotions at the same time, it will, whenever it is afterwards affected by one of these two
-
III-XV. Anything can, accidentally, be the cause of pleasure, pain, or desire.
-
III-XVI. Simply from the fact that we conceive, that a given object has some point of resemblance with another object
-
III-XVII. If we conceive that a thing, which is wont to affect us painfully, has any point of resemblance with another thing
-
III-XVIII. A man is as much affected pleasurably or painfully by the image of a thing past or future as by the image of a thing present.
-
III-XIX. He who conceives that the object of his love is destroyed will feel pain; if he conceives that it is preserved he will feel pleasure.
-
III-XX. He who conceives that the object of his hate is destroyed will also feel pleasure.
-
III-XXI. He who conceives, that the object of his love is affected pleasurably or painfully, will himself be affected pleasurably or painfully
-
III-XXII. If we conceive that anything pleasurably affects some object of our love, we shall be affected with love towards that thing.
-
III-XXIII. He who conceives, that an object of his hatred is painfully affected, will feel pleasure.
-
III-XXIV. If we conceive that anyone pleasurably affects an object of our hate, we shall feel hatred towards him also.
-
III-XXV. We endeavour to affirm, concerning ourselves, and concerning what we love, everything that we can conceive to affect pleasurably ourselves
-
III-XXVI. We endeavour to affirm, concerning that which we hate, everything which we conceive to affect it painfully
-
III-XXVII. By the very fact that we conceive a thing, which is like ourselves, and which we have not regarded with any emotion
-
III-XXVIII. We endeavour to bring about whatsoever we conceive to conduce to pleasure
-
III-XXXI. If we conceive that anyone loves, desires, or hates anything which we ourselves love, desire, or hate
-
III-XXXII. If we conceive that anyone takes delight in something, which only one person can possess
-
III-XXXIII. When we love a thing similar to ourselves we endeavour, as far as we can, to bring about that it should love us in return.
-
III-XXXIV. The greater the emotion with which we conceive a loved object to be affected towards us, the greater will be our complacency.
-
III-XXXV. If anyone conceives, that an object of his love joins itself to another with closer bonds of friendship than he himself has attained to
-
III-XXXVI. He who remembers a thing, in which he has once taken delight, desires to possess it under the same circumstances
-
III-XXXVII. Desire arising through pain or pleasure, hatred or love, is greater in proportion as the emotion is greater.
-
III-XXXVIII. If a man has begun to hate an object of his love, so that love is thoroughly destroyed, he will, causes being equal
-
III-XXXIX. He who hates anyone will endeavour to do him an injury, unless he fears that a greater injury will thereby accrue to himself
-
III-XL. He, who conceives himself to be hated by another, and believes that he has given him no cause for hatred, will hate that other in return.
-
III-XLI. If anyone conceives that he is loved by another, and believes that he has given no cause for such love, he will love that other in return.
-
III-XLII. He who has conferred a benefit on anyone from motives of love or honour will feel pain, if he sees that the benefit is received without gratitude.
-
III-XLIII. Hatred is increased by being reciprocated, and can on the other hand be destroyed by love.
-
III-XLIV. Hatred which is completely vanquished by love passes into love: and love is thereupon greater than if hatred had not preceded it.
-
III-XLV. If a man conceives, that anyone similar to himself hates anything also similar to himself, which he loves, he will hate that person.
-
III-XLVI. If a man has been affected pleasurably or painfully by anyone, of a class or nation different from his own, and if the pleasure or pain
-
III-XLVII. Joy arising from the fact, that anything we hate is destroyed, or suffers other injury, is never unaccompanied by a certain pain in us.
-
III-XLVIII. Love or hatred towards, for instance, Peter is destroyed, if the pleasure involved in the former
-
III-XLIX. Love or hatred towards a thing, which we conceive to be free, must, other conditions being similar
-
III-L. Anything whatever can be, accidentally, a cause of hope or fear.
-
III-LI. Different men may be differently affected by the same object, and the same man may be differently affected at different times by the same object.
-
III-LII. An object which we have formerly seen in conjunction with others, and which we do not conceive to have any property
-
III-LIII. When the mind regards itself and its own power of activity, it feels pleasure
-
III-LIV. The mind endeavours to conceive only such things as assert its power of activity.
-
III-LV. When the mind contemplates its own weakness, it feels pain thereat.
-
III-LVI. There are as many kinds of pleasure, of pain, of desire, and of every emotion compounded of these, such as vacillations of spirit
-
III-LVII. Any emotion of a given individual differs from the emotion of another individual, only in so far as the essence of the one individual
-
III-LVIII. Besides pleasure and desire, which are passivities or passions, there are other emotions derived from pleasure and desire
-
III-LIX. Among all the emotions attributable to the mind as active, there are none which cannot be referred to pleasure or desire.
-
III. ON THE ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE EMOTIONS. DEFINITIONS OF THE EMOTIONS.
-
III. ON THE ORIGIN AND NATURE OF THE EMOTIONS. GENERAL DEFINITION OF THE EMOTIONS.
-
-
-
IV. Of Human Bondage, or the Strength of the Emotions.
-
-
IV. Of Human Bondage, or the Strength of the Emotions. PREFACE.
-
IV. Of Human Bondage, or the Strength of the Emotions. DEFINITIONS.
-
IV. Of Human Bondage, or the Strength of the Emotions. AXIOM.
-
IV. Of Human Bondage, or the Strength of the Emotions. PROPOSITIONS.
-
-
IV-I. No positive quality possessed by a false idea is removed by the presence of what is true, in virtue of its being true.
-
IV-II. We are only passive, in so far as we are apart of Nature, which cannot be conceived by itself without other parts.
-
IV-III. The force whereby a man persists in existing is limited, and is infinitely surpassed by the power of external causes.
-
IV-IV. It is impossible, that man should not be a part of Nature, or that he should be capable of undergoing no changes
-
IV-V. The power and increase of every passion, and its persistence in existing are not defined by the power
-
IV-VI. The force of any passion or emotion can overcome the rest of a man’s activities or power, so that the emotion becomes obstinately fixed to him.
-
IV-VII. An emotion can only be controlled or destroyed by another emotion contrary thereto, and with more power for controlling emotion.
-
IV-VIII. The knowledge of good and evil is nothing else but the emotions of pleasure or pain, in so far as we are conscious thereof.
-
IV-An emotion, whereof we conceive the cause to be with us at the present time, is stronger than if we did not conceive the cause to be with us.
-
IV-X. Towards something future, which we conceive as close at hand, we are affected more intensely
-
IV-XI. An emotion towards that which we conceive as necessary is, when other conditions are equal
-
IV-XII. An emotion towards a thing, which we know not to exist at the present time
-
IV-XIII. Emotion towards a thing contingent, which we know not to exist in the present
-
IV-XIV. A true knowledge of good and evil cannot check any emotion by virtue of being true, but only in so far as it is considered as an emotion.
-
IV-XV. Desire arising from the knowledge of good and bad can be quenched or checked
-
IV-XVI. Desire arising from the knowledge of good and evil, in so far as such knowledge regards what is future
-
IV-XVII. Desire arising from the true knowledge of good and evil, in so far as such knowledge is concerned
-
IV-XVIII. Desire arising from pleasure is, other conditions being equal, stronger than desire arising from pain.
-
IV-XIX. Every man, by the laws of his nature, necessarily desires or shrinks from that which he deems to be good or bad.
-
IV-XX. The more every man endeavours, and is able to seek what is useful to him—in other words
-
IV-XXI. No one can desire to be blessed, to act rightly, and to live rightly
-
IV-XXII. No virtue can be conceived as prior to this endeavour to preserve one’s own being.
-
IV-XXIII. Man, in so far as he is determined to a particular action because he has inadequate ideas
-
IV-XXIV. To act absolutely in obedience to virtue is in us the same thing as to act
-
IV-XXV. No one wishes to preserve his being for the sake of anything else.
-
IV-XXVI. Whatsoever we endeavour in obedience to reason is nothing further than to understand
-
IV-XXVII. We know nothing to be certainly good or evil, save such things as really conduce to understanding
-
IV-XXVIII. The mind’s highest good is the knowledge of God, and the mind’s highest virtue is to know God.
-
IV-XXIX. No individual thing, which is entirely different from our own nature
-
IV-XXX. A thing cannot be bad for us through the quality which it has in common with our nature
-
IV-XXXI. In so far as a thing is in harmony with our nature, it is necessarily good.
-
IV-XXXII. In so far as men are a prey to passion, they cannot, in that respect, be said to be naturally in harmony.
-
IV-XXXIII. Men can differ in nature, in so far as they are assailed by those emotions, which are passions
-
IV-XXXIV. In so far as men are assailed by emotions which are passions, they can be contrary one to another.
-
IV-XXXV. In so far only as men live in obedience to reason, do they always necessarily agree in nature.
-
IV-XXXVI. The highest good of those who follow virtue is common to all, and therefore all can equally rejoice therein.
-
IV-XXXVII. The good which every man, who follows after virtue, desires for himself he will also desire for other men
-
IV-XXXVIII. Whatsoever disposes the human body, so as to render it capable of being affected in an increased number of ways
-
IV-XXXIX. Whatsoever brings about the preservation of the proportion of motion and rest
-
IV-XL. Whatsoever conduces to man’s social life, or causes men to live together in harmony, is useful
-
IV-XLI. Pleasure in itself is not bad but good: contrariwise, pain in itself is bad.
-
IV-XLII. Mirth cannot be excessive, but is always good; contrariwise, Melancholy is always bad.
-
IV-XLIII. Stimulation may be excessive and bad; on the other hand, grief may be good, in so far as stimulation or pleasure is bad.
-
IV-XLIV. Love and desire may be excessive.
-
IV-XLV. Hatred can never be good.
-
IV-XLVI. He, who lives under the guidance of reason, endeavours, as far as possible
-
IV-XLVII. Emotions of hope and fear cannot be in themselves good.
-
IV-XLVIII. The emotions of over—esteem and disparagement are always bad.
-
IV-XLIX. Over—esteem is apt to render its object proud.
-
IV-L. Pity, in a man who lives under the guidance of reason, is in itself bad and useless.
-
IV-LI. Approval is not repugnant to reason, but can agree therewith and arise therefrom.
-
IV-LII. Self—approval may arise from reason, and that which arises from reason is the highest possible.
-
IV-LIII. Humility is not a virtue, or does not arise from reason.
-
IV-LIV. Repentance is not a virtue, or does not arise from reason; but he who repents of an action is doubly wretched or infirm.
-
IV-LV. Extreme pride or dejection indicates extreme ignorance of self.
-
IV-LVI. Extreme pride or dejection indicates extreme infirmity of spirit.
-
IV-LVII. The proud man delights in the company of flatterers and parasites, but hates the company of the high—minded.
-
IV-LVIII. Honour (gloria) is not repugnant to reason, but may arise therefrom.
-
IV-LIX. To all the actions, whereto we are determined by emotion wherein the mind is passive
-
IV-LX. Desire arising from a pleasure or pain, that is not attributable to the whole body
-
IV-LXI. Desire which springs from reason cannot be excessive.
-
IV-LXII. In so far as the mind conceives a thing under the dictates of reason
-
IV-LXIII. He who is led by fear, and does good in order to escape evil, is not led by reason.
-
IV-LXIV. The knowledge of evil is an inadequate knowledge.
-
IV-LXV. Under the guidance of reason we should pursue the greater of two goods and the lesser of two evils.
-
IV-LXVI. We may, under the guidance of reason, seek a greater good in the future in preference to a lesser good in the present
-
IV-LXVII. A free man thinks of death least of all things; and his wisdom is a meditation not of death but of life.
-
IV-LXVIII. If men were born free, they would, so long as they remained free, form no conception of good and evil.
-
IV-LXIX. The virtue of a free man is seen to be as great, when it declines dangers, as when it overcomes them.
-
IV-LXX. The free man, who lives among the ignorant, strives, as far as he can, to avoid receiving favours from them.
-
IV-LXXI. Only free men are thoroughly grateful one to another.
-
IV-LXXII. The free man never acts fraudulently, but always in good faith.
-
IV-LXXIII. The man, who is guided by reason, is more free in a State, where he lives under a general system of law
-
IV. Of Human Bondage, or the Strength of the Emotions. APPENDIX.
-
-
-
V. Of the Power of the Understanding, or of Human Freedom.
-
-
V. Of the Power of the Understanding, or of Human Freedom. PREFACE.
-
V. Of the Power of the Understanding, or of Human Freedom. AXIOMS.
-
V. Of the Power of the Understanding, or of Human Freedom. PROPOSITIONS.
-
-
V-I. Even as thoughts and the ideas of things are arranged and associated in the mind
-
V-II. If we remove a disturbance of the spirit, or emotion, from the thought of an external cause
-
V-III. An emotion, which is a passion, ceases to be a passion, as soon as we form a clear and distinct idea thereof.
-
V-IV. There is no modification of the body, whereof we cannot form some clear and distinct conception.
-
V-V. An emotion towards a thing, which we conceive simply
-
V-VI. The mind has greater power over the emotions and is less subject thereto, in so far as it understands all things as necessary.
-
V-VII. Emotions which are aroused or spring from reason, if we take account of time
-
V-VIII. An emotion is stronger in proportion to the number of simultaneous concurrent causes whereby it is aroused.
-
V-
-
V-X. So long as we are not assailed by emotions contrary to our nature
-
V-XI. In proportion as a mental image is referred to more objects, so is it more frequent, or more often vivid, and occupies the mind more.
-
V-XII. The mental images of things are more easily associated with the images referred to things
-
V-XIII. A mental image is more often vivid, in proportion as it is associated with a greater number of other images.
-
V-XIV. The mind can bring it about, that all bodily modifications or images of things may be referred to the idea of God.
-
V-XV. He who clearly and distinctly understands himself and his emotions loves God
-
V-XVI. This love towards God must hold the chief place in the mind.
-
V-XVII. God is without passions, neither is he affected by any emotion of pleasure or pain.
-
V-XVIII. No one can hate God.
-
V-XIX. He, who loves God, cannot endeavour that God should love him in return.
-
V-XX. This love towards God cannot be stained by the emotion of envy or jealousy
-
V-XXI. The mind can only imagine anything, or remember what is past, while the body endures.
-
V-XXII. Nevertheless in God there is necessarily an idea, which expresses the essence of this or that human body under the form of eternity.
-
V-XXIII. The human mind cannot be absolutely destroyed with the body, but there remains of it something which is eternal.
-
V-XXIV. The more we understand particular things, the more do we understand God.
-
V-XXV. The highest endeavour of the mind, and the highest virtue is to understand things by the third kind of knowledge.
-
V-XXVI. In proportion as the mind is more capable of understanding things by the third kind of knowledge
-
V-XXVII. From this third kind of knowledge arises the highest possible mental acquiescence.
-
V-XXVIII. The endeavour or desire to know things by the third kind of knowledge cannot arise from the first, but from the second kind of knowledge.
-
V-XXIX. Whatsoever the mind understands under the form of eternity
-
V-XXX. Our mind, in so far as it knows itself and the body under the form of eternity
-
V-XXXI. The third kind of knowledge depends on the mind, as its formal cause, in so far as the mind itself is eternal.
-
V-XXXII. Whatsoever we understand by the third kind of knowledge, we take delight in, and our delight is accompanied by the idea of God as cause.
-
V-XXXIII. The intellectual love of God, which arises from the third kind of knowledge, is eternal.
-
V-XXXIV. The mind is, only while the body endures, subject to those emotions which are attributable to passions.
-
V-XXXV. God loves himself with an infinite intellectual love.
-
V-XXXVI. The intellectual love of the mind towards God is that very love of God whereby God loves himself
-
V-XXXVII. There is nothing in nature, which is contrary to this intellectual love, or which can take it away.
-
V-XXXVIII. In proportion as the mind understands more things by the second and third kind of knowledge
-
V-XXXIX. He, who possesses a body capable of the greatest number of activities, possesses a mind whereof the greatest part is eternal.
-
V-XL. In proportion as each thing possesses more of perfection, so is it more active, and less passive
-
V-XLI. Even if we did not know that our mind is eternal, we should still
-
V-XLII. Blessedness is not the reward of virtue, but virtue itself;
-
-
Subscribe to The Empty Robot
Get the latest posts delivered right to your inbox
Spread the word: